Leibniz’s Mill

By: Matthew Battles
January 7, 2013

For many, Alan Turing’s 1950 paper “Computing Machinery and Intelligence” is the quintessential (and essentially hopeful) statement of the possibility of a conscious machine. It’s in this paper, published in the journal Mind, that Turing formulates his infamous test, a variation of a parlor game in which the imitation of human discourse is equated to conscious intelligence. Turing gave the problem compelling and intuitive form, but the question was hardly new. The modern preoccupation with intelligence and consciousness in machines reaches back to Descartes; and G. W. Leibniz gave the problem striking shape nearly two hundred and fifty years before Turing’s time, in proposition 17 of his Monadology:

Imagine there were a machine whose structure produced thought, feeling, and perception. We can conceive its being enlarged while maintaining the same relative proportions among its parts, so that we could walk into it as we walk into a mill.

Suppose we do walk into it. All we would find there are cogs and levers pushing one another, and never anything to account for a perception. So perception must be sought in simple substances, and never in composite things like machines.

Turing acknowledged the objection leveled by Leibniz, by way of analogy to a mind hiding in machinery like the skin of an onion:

In considering the functions of the mind or the brain we fi nd certain operations which we can explain in purely mechanical terms. This we say does not correspond to the real mind: it is a sort of skin which we must strip off if we are to find the real mind. But then in what remains we nd a further skin to be stripped o ff, and so on. Proceeding in this way do we ever come to the “real” mind, or do we eventually come to the skin which has nothing in it? In the latter case the whole mind is mechanical.

Today we tend to correlate consciousness with complexity, taking the awesome neural interconnectedness of the human brain as our paradigmatic polestar. At some infinitesimal level deep within the synaptic warp and weft, many hold (indeed hope), computation imputes consciousness. There are fundamental objections to this perspective — most famously argued by the philosopher John Searle, who concludes that syntax-manipulating symbolic systems (like computer software) alone are unable to produce the semantic relations that, for him, are the sine qua non of conscious intelligence. It’s a big debate, tugging not only at the fabric of philosophy, but computer and cognitive science as well. Thus it’s interesting to note that for Leibniz, complexity was a quality that categorically precluded consciousness: the very manifold, hyperarticulate causal workings of the machine prevent it from converging in the quality of a pure “I” that is the quintessence of conscious being. Leibniz gave the name of entelechy to those simple substances which, to him, were self-sufficiently (and it must be said, tautologically) perfect enough to produce consciousness.

For Turing, consciousness emerges from machinic complexity; for Leibniz, as complexity increases, the possibility of intelligence recedes. Two worldviews, both fixed on the machine, drawing opposite conclusions.

With a short piece of annotated video I’ve illustrated Leibniz’s thought experiment, drawing upon a scene from Lech Majewski’s extraordinary 2011 film The Mill and the Cross that beautifully evokes the arresting philosophical richness of Leibniz’s Mill. Now, Majewski’s film doesn’t have anything to say directly about artificial intelligence; the painting that inspires the movie, Pieter Bruegel’s Christ on the Way to Calvary, was painted two centuries before Leibniz’s time. In the film, Bruegel (played by Rutger Hauer) posits the mill in his painting as a kind of mechanical axis mundi, its stones inexorably grinding our affairs; God the miller keeps the machinery working, but never intervenes in the sowing, cultivation, and winnowing of our sublunar affairs. Down here, suffering and injustice continue, mere grist for the mill — manufactured in the black-boxed entelechies of conscious minds, upon which no machine can operate.

(The piece will only play in Chrome. In the YouTube version of the movie, the scene showing the inner workings of the mill begins at the ten-minute mark. I strongly recommend the entire film, which available via Netflix.)

Share this Post
Share on FacebookShare on Google+Tweet about this on TwitterShare on LinkedInPin on PinterestShare on Tumblr

Categories

Most Visited, Read-outs

Tags

What do you think?

  1. I suppose that’s at the root of 17c dualism really – the opposition between the unextended simplicity and unity of mind versus the extended and divisible complexity of matter. Now we’re much more likely to want to see everything as emerging from the same teaming complexity – Spinoza or Deleuze style. Deleuze wanted Leibniz to open the closed upper floor of his baroque house (another architectural metaphor – maybe for your next film!) onto the complex, teaming openness of the lower floor, the material world. I think there’s a lot of power in classical dualism though that we’ve forgotten about now that the whole Spinozan/Deleuzian ideas of emergence and immanence have become so culturally dominant.

  2. Thanks for this, Matthew! It’s terrific to have you posting at HiLobrow again after too long away. Now I have to get Chrome so I can watch the video…

  3. Loved the Majewski clip, Matthew. I think empirically that neural complexity favors Turing over Liebnitz. The “simpliciy” of self-reflective consciousness is for us a phenominological given only because we apperceive it as such in other members of our species, & it’s not something automatically accorded to other entities; it’s a wonder that society hasn’t regressed to the 17th-18th century limitation to recognising only Caucasian middle-class, middle-aged males as truly human. I hope we can progress much further so that the rest of the galaxy doesn’t have to put us in quarantine, as per either versin of The Day the Earth Stood Still!

  4. I do agree about the empirical favorability of complexity over entelechy in the explication of mind, Sidney. Indeed I want to say that the dualism Louise instances, which has its bases in Leibniz and Descartes, bedevils the study of cognition to this day—it’s the paradigmatic basis of our scientific materialism, after all. Experimental and observational data emerging in the last half century or so are putting a lot of pressure on that materialist paradigm. This fundamental structural element of modern science, which already troubled Goethe, not only complicates the study of mind, but determines much about the place of science in culture, patterning science’s relationship with religion and the humanities in particular. This isn’t to say that the explanation of mind won’t be found in material stuff—instead, that we may need a new paradigm to organize our knowledge of the material, which bequeathed us a science that eschewed anything that seems like subjectivity or spirit. It might be said that Turing offered the first glimpse of a new paradigm founded in an account of computation; today, information theory is arguably the regnant approach to forming an account of consciousness. But there are many who disagree with that approach.

  5. What I’m finding interesting at the moment though – are ways some contemporary thinkers are going back to Descartes and seeing in that dualism possibilities for freedom, negation (in the philosophical sense!) and revolution that the more monistic and immanent models don’t allow for. Zizek’s Cartesianism, for instance, is based on his desire to find ways of ‘jumping out’ of existing co-ordinates and radically negating them – we can only do that if we have ‘somewhere else to go’ and that ‘somewhere else’ can be the cogito taken in its radically negative rather than metaphysically positive sense. I’m also starting to link this up to radical forms of Indian dualism and they give us ways out of the various traps of matter/nature. I think this is a fascinating area and is too complex to write about fully in a comment box – it also has big ramifications for contemporary discourse on ‘mind-body’ and why it could be a bit of a trap to tie these up together too closely. Eg – the way things like obesity become a moral failing because we have tied up mind and body too closely.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published.